Main Article Content
Abstract
Tujuan penelitian ini adalah mengkaji makna keadilan dalam perspektif filsafat hukum aliran utilitarianisme dan positivisme; serta menelaah makna ‘benar’ dan ‘adil’ dalam kacamata filsafat hukum. Jenis penelitian ini adalah penelitian hukum dengan menggunakan pendekatan konseptual dan perbandingan; sebagaimana mengkaji isu hukum menggunakan sudut pandang utilitarianisme dan positivisme. Bahan hukum yang digunakan sebagai referensi penelitian adalah bahan hukum dan bahan non-hukum. Hasil penelitian menunjukkan bahwa sudut pandang utilitarianisme memandang keadilan dan kebahagiaan sebagai orientasi utama; sehingga, aliran utilitarianisme justru memberikan ruang kepada pemutus hukum untuk mempertimbangkan konsekuensi positif dari suatu perbuatan kejahatan. Sedangkan dalam perspektif positivisme, keadilan dianggap sebagai tujuan utama dari hukum; sebagaimana dilatar belakangi oleh pandangan penganut aliran positivisme yang menyatakan makna keadilan sebenarnya adalah manakala keadilan yang tertinggi adalah ketidakadilan yang tertinggi pula. Kemudian, ‘benar’ dan ‘adil’ dalam pandangan utilitarianisme dan positivism menyatakan bahwa suatu hukum dapat dikatakan adil bila memenuhi unsur konstitutif hukum, bukan hanya unsur regulatif hukum semata (adanya peraturan perundang-undangan tertulis).
Keywords
Article Details
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License.
1. Hak cipta atas artikel apa pun dipegang oleh penulisnya.
2. Penulis memberikan jurnal, hak publikasi pertama dengan karya yang dilisensikan secara bersamaan di bawah Lisensi Atribusi Creative Commons yang memungkinkan orang lain untuk membagikan karya dengan pengakuan atas kepenulisan dan publikasi awal karya tersebut dalam jurnal ini.
3. Penulis dapat membuat pengaturan kontrak tambahan yang terpisah untuk distribusi non-eksklusif dari versi jurnal yang diterbitkan dari karya tersebut (misalnya, mempostingnya ke repositori institusional atau menerbitkannya dalam sebuah buku), dengan pengakuan dari publikasi awalnya di jurnal ini.
4. Penulis diizinkan dan didorong untuk memposting karya mereka secara online (misalnya, di repositori institusional atau di situs web mereka) sebelum dan selama proses pengiriman, karena hal itu dapat mengarah pada pertukaran yang produktif, serta kutipan yang lebih awal dan lebih besar dari karya yang diterbitkan.
5. Artikel dan materi terkait yang diterbitkan didistribusikan di bawah Lisensi Internasional Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0
References
- Augustine, A. (2017). THE CONCEPTS OF JUSTICE IN ARISTOTLE ’ S PHILOSOPHY : IMPLICATIONS FOR SOCIO- POLITCAL LIFE IN NIGERIA, XX(2), 155–169.
- Brouwer, R. (2021). Law and Philosophy in the Late Roman Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Collard, D. (2006). Research on Well-Being. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(3), 330–354. Retrieved from http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0048393106289795
- Dickinson, L. A. (2020). The Rule of Law Under Siege, but Which Rule of Law? Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 12(1), 195–204. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/10.1007/s40803-020-00135-1
- Disantara, F. P. (2021). Perspektif Keadilan Bermartabat dalam Paradoks Etika dan Hukum. Jurnal Litigasi, 22(2), 205–229.
- Dworkin, R. (1994). Law, Philosophy and Interpretation. Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 80(4), 463–475.
- Efendi, J., & Ibrahim, J. (2018). Metode Penelitian Hukum: Normatif dan Empiris (Pertama.). Depok: Prenadamedia Group. Retrieved from https://books.google.co.id/books?id=5OZeDwAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=Metode+Penelitian+Hukum:+Normatif+dan+Empiris&hl=en&sa=X&ved=0ahUKEwj1sumo86PmAhXkzzgGHZiSDq0Q6AEIKDAA#v=onepage&q=Metode Penelitian Hukum%3A Normatif dan Empiris&f=false
- Fios, F. (2012). Keadilan Hukum Jeremy Bentham dan Relevansinya bagi Praktik Hukum Kontemporer. Humaniora, 3(1), 299. Retrieved from https://journal.binus.ac.id/index.php/Humaniora/article/view/3315
- Fried, C. (1998). Philosophy Matters. Harvard Law Review, 111(7), 1739. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1342479?origin=crossref
- Friedmann, W. (1961). Legal Philosophy and Judicial Lawmaking. Columbia Law Review, 61(5), 821. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1120096?origin=crossref
- Horn, C. (2020). Aristotle on the Legal and Moral Aspects of Law. Ethics in Ancient Greek Literature (pp. 81–100). De Gruyter. Retrieved from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783110699616-005/html
- HOROWITZ, D. L. (1997). SELF-DETERMINATION: POLITICS, PHILOSOPHY, AND LAW. Nomos, 39, 421–463.
- Husik, I. (1924). The Legal Philosophy of Rudolph Stammler. Columbia Law Review, 24(4), 373. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1114196?origin=crossref
- Jacobs, S. (1990). Bentham, science and the construction of jurisprudence. History of European Ideas, 12(5), 583–594. Retrieved from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1016/0191-6599%2890%2990173-C
- Johnson, L. D., & Koenig, M. L. (2020). Walk the Line: Aristotle and the Ethics of Narrative. Nevada Law Journal, 20(3), 1039–1074.
- Kelly, P. J. (1989). Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: The Civil Law and the Foundations of Bentham’s Economic Thought. Utilitas, 1(1), 62–81. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0953820800000066/type/journal_article
- Kolosov, I. V., & Sigalov, K. E. (2020). WAS J. BENTHAM THE FIRST LEGAL UTILITARIAN? RUDN Journal of Law, 24(2), 438–471. Retrieved from http://journals.rudn.ru/law/article/view/23941
- Kramer, M. H. (2004). Responsibility in Law and Morality. Philosophical Review, 113(1), 133–135. Retrieved from https://read.dukeupress.edu/the-philosophical-review/article/113/1/133-135/2623
- Latipulhayat, A. (2015). Jeremy Bentham. PADJADJARAN Jurnal Ilmu Hukum (Journal of Law), 2(2), 413–424. Retrieved from http://jurnal.unpad.ac.id/pjih/article/view/7342
- Marshall, J. B. (1974). PHILOSOPHY AND LAW. Jurimetrics Journal, 14(3), 171.
- Moll, W. L., & Stammler, R. (1926). The Theory of Justice. Harvard Law Review.
- Naffine, N., & Owens, R. (2019). Intention in Law and Philosophy. Abingdon: Routledge.
- Patterson, D. (2018). Theoretical Disagreement, Legal Positivism, and Interpretation. Ratio Juris, 31(3), 260–275. Retrieved from http://doi.wiley.com/10.1111/raju.12216
- Paulson, S. L. (1994). Lon L. Fuller, Gustav Radbruch, and the “Positivist” Theses. Law and Philosophy, 13(3), 313. Retrieved from http://www.crossref.org/deleted_DOI.html
- Pound, R. (1905). Do We Need a Philosophy of Law? Columbia Law Review, 5(5), 339. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1109546?origin=crossref
- Radbruch, G. (2006). Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law (1946). Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 26(1), 1–11. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/ojls/article-lookup/doi/10.1093/ojls/gqi041
- Radbruch, Gustav. (2020). Law’s Image of the Human. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 40(4), 667–681. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/ojls/article/40/4/667/5927578
- Rawls, J. (1999). The Law of Peoples: With “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited.” Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Rawls, J. (2005). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Sheppard, S. (1998). The Perfectionisms of John Rawls. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 11(2), 383–415. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0841820900002058/type/journal_article
- Summers, R. S. (1963). `Is’ and `Ought’ in Legal Philosophy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 13(51), 157. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/pq/article-lookup/doi/10.2307/2217191
- Tan, S. H. (2021). Radbruch’s Formula Revisited: The Lex Injusta Non Est Lex Maxim in Constitutional Democracies. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 34(2), 461–491. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0841820921000126/type/journal_article
- Tasioulas, J. (Ed.). (2020). The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Twining, W. (2019). Bentham’s Theory of Evidence: Setting a Context. Journal of Bentham Studies, 18(1), 20–37. Retrieved from https://scienceopen.com/document?vid=72c80ce1-6261-4b9e-afe8-0663589607c9
- Augustine, A. (2017). THE CONCEPTS OF JUSTICE IN ARISTOTLE ’ S PHILOSOPHY : IMPLICATIONS FOR SOCIO- POLITCAL LIFE IN NIGERIA, XX(2), 155–169.
- Brouwer, R. (2021). Law and Philosophy in the Late Roman Republic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Collard, D. (2006). Research on Well-Being. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 36(3), 330–354. Retrieved from http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0048393106289795
- Dickinson, L. A. (2020). The Rule of Law Under Siege, but Which Rule of Law? Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, 12(1), 195–204. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/10.1007/s40803-020-00135-1
- Disantara, F. P. (2021). Perspektif Keadilan Bermartabat dalam Paradoks Etika dan Hukum. Jurnal Litigasi, 22(2), 205–229.
- Dworkin, R. (1994). Law, Philosophy and Interpretation. Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 80(4), 463–475.
- Efendi, J., & Ibrahim, J. (2018). Metode Penelitian Hukum: Normatif dan Empiris (Pertama.). Depok: Prenadamedia Group. Retrieved from https://books.google.co.id/books?id=5OZeDwAAQBAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=Metode+Penelitian+Hukum:+Normatif+dan+Empiris&hl=en&sa=X&ved=0ahUKEwj1sumo86PmAhXkzzgGHZiSDq0Q6AEIKDAA#v=onepage&q=Metode Penelitian Hukum%3A Normatif dan Empiris&f=false
- Fios, F. (2012). Keadilan Hukum Jeremy Bentham dan Relevansinya bagi Praktik Hukum Kontemporer. Humaniora, 3(1), 299. Retrieved from https://journal.binus.ac.id/index.php/Humaniora/article/view/3315
- Fried, C. (1998). Philosophy Matters. Harvard Law Review, 111(7), 1739. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1342479?origin=crossref
- Friedmann, W. (1961). Legal Philosophy and Judicial Lawmaking. Columbia Law Review, 61(5), 821. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1120096?origin=crossref
- Horn, C. (2020). Aristotle on the Legal and Moral Aspects of Law. Ethics in Ancient Greek Literature (pp. 81–100). De Gruyter. Retrieved from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9783110699616-005/html
- HOROWITZ, D. L. (1997). SELF-DETERMINATION: POLITICS, PHILOSOPHY, AND LAW. Nomos, 39, 421–463.
- Husik, I. (1924). The Legal Philosophy of Rudolph Stammler. Columbia Law Review, 24(4), 373. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1114196?origin=crossref
- Jacobs, S. (1990). Bentham, science and the construction of jurisprudence. History of European Ideas, 12(5), 583–594. Retrieved from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1016/0191-6599%2890%2990173-C
- Johnson, L. D., & Koenig, M. L. (2020). Walk the Line: Aristotle and the Ethics of Narrative. Nevada Law Journal, 20(3), 1039–1074.
- Kelly, P. J. (1989). Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: The Civil Law and the Foundations of Bentham’s Economic Thought. Utilitas, 1(1), 62–81. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0953820800000066/type/journal_article
- Kolosov, I. V., & Sigalov, K. E. (2020). WAS J. BENTHAM THE FIRST LEGAL UTILITARIAN? RUDN Journal of Law, 24(2), 438–471. Retrieved from http://journals.rudn.ru/law/article/view/23941
- Kramer, M. H. (2004). Responsibility in Law and Morality. Philosophical Review, 113(1), 133–135. Retrieved from https://read.dukeupress.edu/the-philosophical-review/article/113/1/133-135/2623
- Latipulhayat, A. (2015). Jeremy Bentham. PADJADJARAN Jurnal Ilmu Hukum (Journal of Law), 2(2), 413–424. Retrieved from http://jurnal.unpad.ac.id/pjih/article/view/7342
- Marshall, J. B. (1974). PHILOSOPHY AND LAW. Jurimetrics Journal, 14(3), 171.
- Moll, W. L., & Stammler, R. (1926). The Theory of Justice. Harvard Law Review.
- Naffine, N., & Owens, R. (2019). Intention in Law and Philosophy. Abingdon: Routledge.
- Patterson, D. (2018). Theoretical Disagreement, Legal Positivism, and Interpretation. Ratio Juris, 31(3), 260–275. Retrieved from http://doi.wiley.com/10.1111/raju.12216
- Paulson, S. L. (1994). Lon L. Fuller, Gustav Radbruch, and the “Positivist” Theses. Law and Philosophy, 13(3), 313. Retrieved from http://www.crossref.org/deleted_DOI.html
- Pound, R. (1905). Do We Need a Philosophy of Law? Columbia Law Review, 5(5), 339. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/1109546?origin=crossref
- Radbruch, G. (2006). Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law (1946). Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 26(1), 1–11. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/ojls/article-lookup/doi/10.1093/ojls/gqi041
- Radbruch, Gustav. (2020). Law’s Image of the Human. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 40(4), 667–681. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/ojls/article/40/4/667/5927578
- Rawls, J. (1999). The Law of Peoples: With “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited.” Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Rawls, J. (2005). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Sheppard, S. (1998). The Perfectionisms of John Rawls. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 11(2), 383–415. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0841820900002058/type/journal_article
- Summers, R. S. (1963). `Is’ and `Ought’ in Legal Philosophy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 13(51), 157. Retrieved from https://academic.oup.com/pq/article-lookup/doi/10.2307/2217191
- Tan, S. H. (2021). Radbruch’s Formula Revisited: The Lex Injusta Non Est Lex Maxim in Constitutional Democracies. Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 34(2), 461–491. Retrieved from https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0841820921000126/type/journal_article
- Tasioulas, J. (Ed.). (2020). The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Twining, W. (2019). Bentham’s Theory of Evidence: Setting a Context. Journal of Bentham Studies, 18(1), 20–37. Retrieved from https://scienceopen.com/document?vid=72c80ce1-6261-4b9e-afe8-0663589607c9